INTEGRAL STUDIES

presents a

 

GUEST AUTHOR

 

DHRUV PATEL

School of Law
University of Manchester

 

 

Referenda: Plebiscites or Opinion Polls

An Analysis of the Use, Constitutionality and

Appropriateness of Direct Democracy in

the British Constitution

 


 

 


published 2005 by

INTEGRAL STUDIES

Guildford and Berlin

e-mail integral@iniref.org






1.   CONTENTS

 

1.      CONTENTS......................................................................................................................

 

2.      INTRODUCTION............................................................................................................

2.1.       Definitions................................................................................................................

 

3.      THE USE OF DIRECT DEMOCRACY  IN BRITAIN SO FAR...................................

3.1.       From Despised to Beloved: the Heyday of an Unpopular Device............................

3.2.       Analyses : Not Yet a Constitutional Safeguard........................................................

3.3.       The Binding Nature of the Referendum..................................................................

 

4.      IS DIRECT DEMOCRACY CONSTITUTIONAL?.....................................................

4.1.       Defining the Constitution.......................................................................................

4.2.       Direct Democracy and Parliamentary Sovereignty...............................................

4.2.1.        The Traditional Approach...............................................................................

4.2.2.        Sovereignty Redefined...................................................................................

4.2.3.        A Reconciliation Proposed.............................................................................

4.3.       A New Constitutional Convention?........................................................................

4.4.       The Constitutionality of Direct Democracy............................................................

 

5.      HOW APPROPRIATE IS DIRECT DEMOCRACY FOR THE UK?.........................

5.1.       Desirability............................................................................................................

5.1.1.        The Case For..................................................................................................

5.1.2.        Dismissal of the Case Against........................................................................

5.2.       The Feasibility of Referendums..............................................................................

5.2.1.        Sovereign Subjects.........................................................................................

5.2.2.        Voting Systems and Majorities......................................................................

5.2.3.        The Timing of the Vote..................................................................................

5.2.4.        The Question to be Put...................................................................................

5.2.5.        Money Matters...............................................................................................

5.2.6.        The influence of Mass Media.........................................................................

5.2.7.        Political Influence...........................................................................................

5.3.       Does Direct Democracy Always Lead to Good Decision-Making?.......................

5.4.       Direct Democracy in its Most Suitable Form........................................................

5.4.1.        The Most Appropriate Form of Referendum..................................................

5.4.2.        The Most Appropriate Form of CitizensÕ Initiative........................................

 

6.      CONCLUSIONS............................................................................................................

 

7.      APPENDICES................................................................................................................

7.1.       Table of Major Referendums in the UK.................................................................

 

8.      BIBLIOGRAPHY..........................................................................................................

8.1.       Books.....................................................................................................................

8.2.       Articles...................................................................................................................

8.3.       Official Publications...............................................................................................

8.4.       Electronic Resources..............................................................................................

8.5.       Cases Referred to...................................................................................................

8.6.       Statutes Referred to................................................................................................

8.7.       Miscellaneous Resources.......................................................................................


9.      REFERENCES................................................................................................................



2.  INTRODUCTION

This paper is an investigation into the changing nature of the referendum in light of contemporary British constitutional reform. Clement Atlee once said that ÒreferendumsÉare just not BritishÓ[1], but they are now indisputably an important part of the British decision-making process.  The growth in the use and popularity of referenda in the intervening years will be examined.  It will be shown that whilst the growing use of a previously alien device is to be commended this has regrettably occurred as a result of political expediency rather than the political and constitutional recognition of popular sovereignty.

 

A solution to the long-standing debate about the constitutionality Ð or lack thereof Ð of referendums will be proffered.  Bagehot wrote that Òthe unresolved role of the people in the constitution lies at the heart of arguments aboutÉreferendums.Ó[2] If popular sovereignty is accepted, it follows that referendums have binding force; if the old principle of parliamentary sovereignty is retained, then referendums will remain mere Ôopinion pollsÕ.  BagehotÕs conundrum would quickly evaporate if the law recognised that in practice sovereignty rests with the people.

 

A case for a continuing use of referenda in the United Kingdom will be made.  It will be shown that all arguments against referenda can be dismissed with relative ease, without going so far as arguing that opponents of referendums are indeed opponents of democracy.

 

Whilst more than 98% of states have used referendums[3], it is unwise to assume that they are always appropriate.  The feasibility of the referendum will be considered and it will be shown that despite its shortcomings the referendum Ð used wisely Ð is an appropriate, valuable and progressive tool particularly in light information technology advances and e-democracy. 

 

Voting at general and local elections aside, the referendum is the only contact point between the people, the legislature and the executive.  The constitution currently precludes the citizensÕ initiative and it has yet to find favour with politicians.  Whether the initiative should be legitimised in Britain will be investigated.  Of particular interest here is the governmentÕs motivation for its U-turn with respect to a referendum on the European constitutional treaty.

 

A thin line divides constitutional law and political science.  This paper will, out of necessity, straddle the two and offer debate focussing on the referendum grounded in constitutional principles.

2.1.          Definitions

 

It is important to define important terms before proceeding.  ÔReferendumsÕ should be taken to mean Òa mechanism which allows voters to make a choice between the alternative courses of action on a particular issue.Ó[4]  Whilst ÔplebisciteÕ means an ordinance of self-determination with binding authority.[5]  A CitizensÕ Initiative is a process whereby a significant body of popular opinion can automatically trigger a referendum or debate in Parliament.


 

 

 

3.  THE USE OF DIRECT DEMOCRACY  IN BRITAIN SO FAR

3.1.  From Despised to Beloved: the Heyday of an Unpopular Device

There is no tradition of referendums in the United Kingdom[6], nor is there a longstanding expectation amongst the people of consultation regarding major constitutional innovations[7].  The Liberal Party first suggested that a referendum be employed in 1969 to solve the deep divisions across the country with regard to membership of the EEC.  But, neither of the main parties took referendum proposals seriously[8] and subsequently opposed a referendum on the issue in the 1970 General Election.[9]  Prime Minister Harold Wilson quickly rejected a referendum on entry into the EEC: ÒThe constitutional position is that whatever this House decides in this matter, or any other matter, is the right decisionÓ[10].  Yet despite this deep distrust and wide unpopularity, the referendum has enjoyed thirty golden years.

 

Until the 1970s referendums were widely considered to be prima-facie antagonistic to the central principle of the British Constitution Ð parliamentary sovereignty[11] - and therefore unconstitutional[12].  Even the 1975 referendum on the EC was seen by the then Labour government as a unique event. Four days after the referendum in 1975 Sir John Eden, a conservative backbencher, asked Prime Minister Harold Wilson, ÒWill he keep to his determination not to repeat the constitutional experiment of the Referendum?Ó To which he replied ÒI certainly give the right Honourable MemberÉthe assurance he seeks.Ó[13]  However backbench pressure subsequently forced the government to concede referendums on devolution to both Scotland and Wales.[14]  Nevertheless until the election of ÔNew LabourÕ in 1997 only four referendums had been held.[15]

 

However, an unprecedented number of referendums have been held in the last seven years.[16]  There have been a further four major pre- and post-legislative referendums[17] and no less than thirty local referendums on directly-appointed mayors.[18]  Three further referendums have been promised: a referendum on the voting system for the House of Commons,[19] a referendum on the adoption of the Euro and a referendum on the European Constitutional Treaty.  It is particularly interesting that the decisions to hold these referendums were uncontroversial Ð the referendum device was not criticised by opposition parties or from within the government[20].  This is of huge importance; less than 30 years ago the referendum was considered constitutionally impossible.  In May 2002 John Prescott issued advice to local authorities on how to use the referendum to consult voters on council tax.  And Nick Raynsford threatened to use local referendums as a means to cap council taxes across the country in September 2003.  Nigel Smith[21] notes that this Òbetrays another characteristic of referendums initiated by governments: they sometimes use them as instruments to further policy and not as a key to genuine choice and decision by the voters.Ó[22]

 

Undoubtedly the referenda held so far have set a precedent.  The argument that referenda are unconstitutional is now unsustainable.[23]  Furthermore, the introduction of the Political Parties, Elections and Referendums Act 2000 (PPERA) is evidential of an intention to hold further referendums.  It must be remembered, however, that whilst the referendum enjoys unprecedented popularity with the current government,[24] it is still a discretional device.  A simple change in government could result in the referendum falling from political grace.


3.2.  Analyses : Not Yet a Constitutional Safeguard

Every referendum held to date has concerned a constitutional issue: the transfer of legislative power[25].  Whilst the referenda are indicative of the recognition of the constitutionality of the transfer of legislative power, did this constitutional status trigger the referendum or were the decisions to hold referendums motivated by other factors?  It is submitted that referendums were and still are held on an ad-hoc basis.  The referendum is an expedient device, appointed when a particular situation calls for a popular verdict[26] and is not yet a true constitutional safeguard.

 

This is demonstrated by the reasons behind each referendum.  The twin devolution referendums of 1979 were forced upon CallaghanÕs government by an alliance of the opposition parties and Labour rebels[27] which was Òdefensive from the start.Ó[28] Referenda are allegedly employed by the current Labour government as a Ôproblem solvingÕ mechanism Ð once a question has been put few can argue with the result.  It is interesting to note the governmentÕs U-turn regarding a referendum for the EC constitution.[29]   If one assumes - as one might - that the decision was a political one, motivated by fears of a backlash from the voters, MPs and party members who were clamouring for a referendum, then what we see is the power of the People in effecting a referendum.  This is a remarkable step forward.  Worldwide Òthe tradition is spreading, as more and more countries with no legal need to have referendums feel impelled to hold them at crucial junctures.Ó[30] 

 

But there remains no formula for initiating referendums, they do not arise as a necessary mechanism of constitutional change[31] but are ÔgrantedÕ at the whim of the government. The only constitutional principle involved is that parliamentary sovereignty remains intact.[32] Indeed it is surprising that given the large majority commanded by the Prime Minister in the House of Commons, he is willing to risk his policies at referendum when there is nothing in law compelling him to do so[33].  Remarkably, most of those who advocate the use of referendums in the UK do so because they believe that they can defeat an innovation that would otherwise go through parliament unopposed[34].

 

Before the call for Òa new regulatory framework for referendumsÓ[35] by the Committee on Standards in Public Life in 1996 and the resulting PPERA 2000 the referendum process was unregulated.   ÒNo coherent, consistent principles were applied in their operation.Ó[36] The PPERA gave the responsibility for administering a referendum to the Electoral Commission, providing for referendums generally for the first time. If the increasing use of the referendum has fostered an environment where referendums are expected as a matter of course, then the PPERA has propped open the floodgates.

 

In most states referendums are held as and when they are required by the constitution rather than for any ulterior or political purpose.[37]  This is how it should be[38].  They operate for the reasons originally advocated by Dicey: to provide a Ôcheck and balanceÕ on the power of the government. 

3.3.          The Binding Nature of the Referendum

 

When questions of the binding nature of referenda arise, the mindset of key individuals is crucial.  In law referendums are nothing more than advisory.[39]  This should not come as a surprise.[40]  At the time of the EC referendum, Edward Short, the leader of the House of Commons remarked, Òthe Government will be bound by it, but Parliament of course, cannot be bound by itÉalthough one would not expect the honourable members to go against the wishes of the people, they remain free to do so.Ó

 

Nevertheless it can be concluded that whilst in law the referendum will be advisory, in practice the result will be binding - but only because the politicians consider it to be so[41].  The binding nature of the referendum can be further demonstrated by asking whether legislation approved by referendum could be repealed without legislative approval.  For example could the Welsh Parliament be abolished without first consulting the Welsh People? Ð surely not.  Despite the obviously binding nature of the referendum, some constitutional commentators insist on claiming that to date no binding referendums have been held, and that to do so would seriously undermine principles of governmental responsibility.[42]

 


 

4.  IS DIRECT DEMOCRACY CONSTITUTIONAL?

 

When Dicey first advocated the referendum in England,[43] his friend James Bryce asked him two questions that remain pertinent to the constitutionality of direct democracy in Great Britain today:

 

1.              ÒWhat is to be the authority to decide when a bill should be referred [to the people]Ó

2.              ÒHow can Ôconstitutional changesÕ be defined in a country which has no rigid constitutionÓ[44]

 

Mads Qvortrup suggests that the popularity of the referendum clouds the question of constitutionality.[45]  It is submitted, however, that the reverse is true.  As referendums become increasingly popular, the importance of their constitutionality rises proportionately.  Until the constitutionality of direct democracy is thoroughly examined, the status of referendums and initiatives lies in the balance.

 

4.1.          Defining the Constitution

 

It is difficult to theoretically analyse that which we cannot even identify.[46] And it is prima-facie impossible to decide Ð with any reasonable level of accuracy Ð whether or not direct democracy is constitutional when only one thing about the constitution is certain: that itÕs borders are elusive.[47] 

 

Britain is almost unique insofar as it lacks a written constitution.[48]  The Constitution Committee has adopted, as its working definition of the constitution Òthe set of laws, rules and practices that create the basic institutions of the state, and its component and related parts, and stipulate the powers of those institutions and the relationships between the different institutions and the relationship between the different institutions and between those institutions and individuals.Ó[49]  Blackstone saw Òthat the king can do no wrongÓ as the central pillar of the constitution.[50]   As the cabinet and parliament replaced the King and his court, Dicey noted that Òthere is no law which Parliament cannot change.  There is no fundamental or so-called constitutional lawÓ[51] and that there is not body of persons Òwhich can pronounce invalid any enactment passed by the British Parliament on the ground of such enactment being opposed to the constitution.Ó[52]  Under any of these analyses the constitution can be whatever the Queen in Parliament enacts. It is submitted that whilst we are moving closer to an answer, the second of BryceÕs questions remains unanswered. If the constitution is indeed Ôwhatever the Queen in Parliament enactsÕ then referendal precedent and the PPERA confirm the referendumÕs constitutionality.

4.2. Direct Democracy and Parliamentary Sovereignty[53]

4.2.1.        The Traditional Approach

 

Parliamentary sovereignty and direct democracy are traditionally antagonistic. Historically the House of Commons would refuse ÔsupplyÕ until grievances had been redressed:  it represented the people.  In passing the 1911 Parliament Act, Parliament declared its own sovereignty[54] such that in law it will always be for parliament to decide the law of the land[55].   The House of LordsÕ Ôreferendal theoryÕ[56] redefined the roles of both Houses and the electors.[57]  Unfortunately the role of British subject is limited to periodically approving preselected Members of Parliament who propose policies and lead public affairs.[58]  In Ellen Street Estates Ltd v. Minster of Health[59] Maugham LJ said, Òthe legislature cannot according to our constitution bind itself as to the form of subsequent legislation, and it is impossible for Parliament to enact that in a subsequent statute dealing with the same subject matter there can be no implied repeal.  If in a subsequent Act Parliament chooses to make it plain that the earlier statute is being to some extent repealed, effect must be given to that intention just because it is the will of the legislature.Ó[60]  It follows that Parliament cannot bind itself to follow the result of a subsequent referendum. It would however be political suicide for the government of the day to contradict a referendum result. 

 

Charter 88 claims that Òin major constitutional matters, the people ought to be consulted. It is not incompatible with Parliamentary sovereignty that there should also be popular sovereignty, where people have a direct say.Ó[61]  It is submitted that they are mistaken; there is no room for true direct democracy in a constitution based on parliamentary sovereignty. As long as parliamentary sovereignty is the central pillar of the constitution, a referendum decision will be, in the eyes of the constitution, no more than an expression of the popular opinion. At the heart of Direct Democracy is the opinion that sovereignty in the United Kingdom rests with the people, that the people should be able to express their wish and that wish be enacted into law.  If a referendum result was to conflict with parliamentary opinion, the honourable members should be legally obliged to accept the decision of their electors.  They are currently free to ignore popular opinion at the risk of provoking outrage and sacrificing their tenures.

 

Bagehot wrote that ultimate authority in the United Kingdom rests with the House of Commons Ð suggesting that once appointed parliamentarians are free to decide as they like, with no reference to their electors.  He described the power of the head of the executive to Òovercome the resistance of the second chamber by choosing new members of that chamberÓ[62] as Òthe safety valve of the truest kind.  It enables the popular will Ð the will of which the executive is the exponent, the will of which it is the appointee Ð to carry out within the constitution desires and conceptions which one branch of the constitution dislikes and resists.Ó  This so-called safety valve allowed the Houses of Commons to ensure that its legislation was not unduly withheld, but did not protect against a tyrannical house or a house under the control of a tyrannical executive.   Interestingly this Ôtrump cardÕ was played to force the introduction of the Parliament Act.  However it is submitted that Bagehot placed too much trust in the House of Commons.[63]  Furthermore, the safety valve which he talks of no longer exists and the danger Ð as it then was Ð of the House of Lords blocking legislation proposed by the elected house is no more.  The danger now, is of the executive enacting legislation that is not supported by the people Ð and there is no valve net to prevent such an atrocity.

 

Interestingly, the American constitution does not place sovereignty anywhere Ð its writers feared that to do so would fuel tyranny.[64]  Is such a position desirable? If so the status quo should be maintained.  But Wade warns us that Òthe body which exercises sovereignty may well be more dangerous to stability that in the days when parliament commanded universal respect.  It must not be forgotten that the inevitable consequence of the Supremacy of Parliament in the legislative field is that there can be no check upon the unscrupulous use of power by a Government which finds itself in command of a majority in the House of Commons.Ó[65]

 

4.2.2.        Sovereignty Redefined

 

Traditionally the House of Commons drew its ÔparliamentaryÕ sovereignty from the Royal Prerogative Ð this is an outdated and fundamentally unjust model.  The crown, as a matter of convention, has no control over the House of Commons or the course of legislation in the UK.  There must be a supreme authority, Òa conclusive power, in every point somewhere.Ó[66]  The time has come to recognise the essence of DiceyÕs theory in law: that the constitution is in practice based on popular sovereignty[67].   ÒDicey identified parliamentary sovereignty as the fundamental norm of the British Constitution.  But, he distinguished between Parliament as the legal sovereign and the People[68] as the political sovereign.Ó[69]  In advocating the referendum Dicey promoted the legal recognition of the political position.

 

The cabinet system relies on parliamentary sovereignty and Òis saved from being an autocratic instrument by the knowledge that at intervals the electorate may alter the composition of the Commons and so place the supremacy of Parliament in other hands but it is the political supremacy rather than the legal doctrine which saves the democratic principle.Ó[70]  That a political doctrine is necessary demonstrates that the constitution is lacking.  This is further evidence that the ÔlegalÕ seat of sovereignty is misplaced.

 

4.2.3.        A Reconciliation Proposed

 

Aristotle wrote that Òthe majority ought to be sovereign, rather than the best, where the best are fewÉ[a] feast to which all contribute is better than one given at one manÕs expense.Ó[71] If one accepts that policy in the UK is largely driven by the majority, and also accepts DiceyÕs Ôobvious conclusionÕ[72] that policy is driven by the sovereignÕs opinionÓ[73] then the sovereign and the people are indistinguishable. The electorate trusts its representatives to apply their minds to legislate, but they are not given the authority to delegate their power.  Bogdanor suggests that such a power Òcan only be obtained through a specific mandateÓ Ð a referendum.[74] Even though Dicey was of the opinion that there is no law in the state which parliament can not change,[75] he took his argument one step further when arguing that in practice the people must consent to all constitutional change in Britain[76].

 

John Austin saw MPs as trustees for their electors in so far as they are able to impose their will on parliament in the long term.  But there is no check on their power between elections.  Dicey maintained that there was a Òdualist systemÓ in the United Kingdom: that in reality the consent of the people for constitutional change was sought whilst in law, such an idea was abhorrent.[77]  He claimed that the existing British constitution already recognised the people as the political sovereign.[78]  Bogdanor believes that, as Dicey foresaw, the referendum has in practice become Òan instrument of entrenchmentÓ  since it Òprevents the powers of Parliament from being transferred without the approval of the peopleÓ [79] He is implying a shift in sovereignty. Whilst this may have occurred in ÔrealÕ or ÔpracticalÕ terms, in law the position has remained the same.  Dicey wrote that the referendum was Òthe one available check on the recklessness of party leaders [and it would yield] formal acknowledgement of the doctrine which lies at the basis of English democracy Ð that a law depends at bottom for its enactment on the consent of the nation as represented by the electors.Ó[80]  The next logical step is the legal acceptance of this doctrine.

 

4.3.          A New Constitutional Convention?

 

Constitutional conventions are Òrules for determining the mode in which the discretionary powers of the Crown (or of the Ministers as servants of the Crown) ought to be exercised.Ó[81]  Vernon Bogdanor reminds us that Òof the recent constitutional reforms, most of them have been validated by referendumÓ[82] and in particular suggests that a convention may have been established that Òthe powers of parliament should not be transferred without popular consent.Ó[83]  Whether such a convention exists will be examined below.

 

By accepting the existence of such a convention we could circumvent all controversial questions of parliamentary sovereignty yet snugly incorporate referenda into the constitution.  For this to be acceptable a supplementary convention would have to be accepted: that the decision is binding on the commons.  There is evidence to support the existence of such a convention. At the time of the 1975 referendum on whether or not Britain should remain in the EC, Edward Short, the leader of the House of Commons declared that Òthe government will be bound by it, but Parliament, of course, cannot be bound by it.Ó[84]  It is unlikely that politicians will not accept the result of a referendum.  Tony Benn, who had come under criticism from the Prime Minister during the 1975 campaign, said: Òwhen the British people speak, everyone, including members of Parliament, should tremble before their decisions and thatÕs certainly the spirit with which I accept the result of the referendumÓ[85].  As so long as the politicians consider referendums binding upon them, a convention will exist.  It is suggested that Ð the introduction of a written constitution and a recognition in law of the sovereignty of the people aside -  the development of conventions for referendums is the only way to prevent political expediency from being the dominant factor in British referendums.[86]

 

An argument against the existence of a convention is that all but one of the referendums held to date (Northern Ireland in 1973) have been held by Labour governments Ð thus the referendal mechanism of constitutional change has not yet been practiced by all parties.  However the Liberal Democrats (and the Liberals before them) favour the use of referendums for any constitutional change, and the Conservatives have advocate referendums in certain situations[87].  It is submitted that any future government would find it difficult to enact major constitutional change without referendal approval.

 

4.4.          The Constitutionality of Direct Democracy

 

The closest the UK gets to entrenched direct democracy is a general commitment in the Northern Ireland Constitution Act[88] Òthat Northern Ireland in its entirety remains part of the United Kingdom and shall not cease to be so without the consent of a majority of the people of Northern Ireland voting in a poll.Ó[89]  However any such poll still requires parliamentary ratification.[90]  Some maintain, Òthere is no legal or constitutional basis for holding a referendum in the UK other than that granted by an Act of Parliament.  The doctrine of supremacy of Parliament gives all power to parliament (and in effect to the Commons) to decide whether or not to seek the advice of the electorate.Ó[91] They argue that the principle of parliamentary sovereignty is so central to the British constitution, that to move away from it slightly Ðlet alone abolish it altogether Ð would be unconstitutional.  Such analyses conclude that the referendum can never be incorporated into the British constitution, let alone be seen as a fundamental machine of the constitutional reform process.   Another quick argument against the constitutionality of direct democracy is that Òthe UK doesnÕt have any citizens Ð only subjects (of the crown).  Until we move beyond the present Ôconstitutional monarchyÕ Ð which isnÕt constitutional at all and would probably be better called conventional monarchy (i.e. everything is based on convention rather than law) Ð you couldnÕt even contemplate the type of citizen based system which exists in ÔpurerÕ democracies.Ó[92]

 

These arguments are fallacious.  Direct democracy is constitutional on two different grounds.  Firstly, if the real base of sovereignty is accepted then claims that direct democracy is constitutional are irrefutable.  Secondly, there is a strong case for concluding that two constitutional conventions exist, one that a referendum must be held before any significant change is made to the constitution and two that the decision of that referendum be binding on the legislature.

 

The argument that direct democracy is inconsistent with parliamentary sovereignty has lost its validity.[93]  The Commission on the Conduct of referendums claims that since Òparliament has sovereign power, it must have the power to call a referendumÓ.  But this is an oversimplification Ð it is submitted that the people are sovereign and parliament is  under a moral obligation to call a referendum. Under BlackstoneÕs interpretation of the common law, the referendum is permissible.  Furthermore, referenda are consistent with the social contract doctrine developed by Locke, Kant and Rousseau[94]. Interestingly under the American Constitution a referendum cannot be characterised as a delegation of power.  The American constitution assumes that Òall power derives from the peopleÓ[95]

 

Furthermore there is no reason why an ordinary Act of Parliament could not state a referendum to be binding or to be required before constitutional change.  Exactly such a provision appears in the Australian Constitution Act (Queensland) 1867[96].  However, whilst Parliament cannot ÔignoreÕ its own legislation it could impliedly repeal it in the ordinary manner regardless of the first act. What is important here is that the MPs will likely consider the provisions as effectively binding.  Bogdanor claims that Òin general, a referendum will bind both Government and ParliamentÓ[97] and as long as it does so, it will have an effect on the constitution.  Under any analysis of what is ÔconstitutionalÕ a mechanism for its change is inherently included within it.

 

Under these analysis, both referendums and citizensÕ initiatives  should be considered constitutional.  However there are no precedents for citizens initiatives in the UK and expression of popular opinion have been ignored more often than not.




5.  HOW APPROPRIATE IS DIRECT DEMOCRACY FOR THE UK?

5.1.          Desirability

 

It is simply asked whether embracing direct democracy is more desirable than the current model of indirect democracy? 

 

Rousseau argued that indirect democracy is not democracy properly so called. He claimed, Òthe people of England think they are free.  They are gravely mistaken. They are free only during the election of Members of Parliament.Ó[98]  However, the Athenian model[99]  would be expensive and impractical.  Magleby concluded that Òpeople who believe in undiluted representative democracy place the higher value on the virtues of stability, compromise, moderation, and access for all segments of the community, regardless of how small and seek institutional arrangements that insulate fundamental principles from short-term fluctuations in public opinion. People who believe in coming as close as possible to direct democracy place the highest value of the virtues of charge, participation, competition, conflict, and majority rule and seek institutional arrangements that maximise rapid and full responses to what particular majorities want.Ó[100] 

 

It is submitted that the most appropriate solution is a system of compromise entrenched in law that incorporates both direct and indirect democracy, allowing a certain degree of flexibility yet entrenching minority rights.  With the problem of popular and parliamentary sovereignty solved, such a middle ground can be found.  Wallace- Macpherson finds that Òthe assumption that ÔdirectÕ and ÔrepresentativeÕ forms of  democracy are bound to be in conflict is (a) likely to be self-fulfilling prophecy and (b) not entirely correct either historically or prospectively.Ó[101] A case will be made for a move towards such a system and the arguments against referendums will be dismissed.

 

5.1.1.        The Case For

 

Rodney Brazier states that Òquestions relating to the fundamental structures of the constitution are of a higher order of importance than those in other areas of national policy, and that in itself is a reason for resorting to unusual methods to resolve them.Ó[102]  Why this is the case is examined below.

 

Democracy, of necessity, dispenses Òa sort of equality to equals and unequals alike.Ó[103]   Yet Bagehot noticed that BritainÕs political arrangements reflected not a participatory but a deferential political culture.[104]  Richard Lung explains partisan EuropeÕs mistake: Òit thinks its elections are representative, when they are mainly referential.  Even where party lists are ÔopenÕÉthe voters are left with a corporate veto for a party that is really only a manifesto referendum vote.Ó[105] Our MPs have become representatives of and responsible to their parties rather than their electors.  As the executive dominates the legislature, the principles of a free constitution are disappearing.[106]  Furthermore MinistersÕ extensive use of the wide range of prerogative powers weakens ministerial accountability to parliament.[107]  This results in a tenuous link between the people from whom authority is derived and the people who exercise it.  Direct democracy will address such problems.

 

When studying the sovereignty of Parliament, Dicey showed that the certain alleged limitations on the power of Parliament did not exist. ÒHe shows how the resolutions of one parliament cannot alter the law; that sovereignty as a matter of law does not lie in the electorate, whose right is restricted to choosing members of Parliament; nor yet in the law courts, where even if a decision is equivalent to judicial legislation it remains subject to repeal by Parliament.Ó[108]  The greater problem is not the lack of a constitutional check on the power of parliament, but of check on the power of the Prime Minister and the small number of ministers who comprise the cabinet and who use party whips to ensure compliance from the House.  Nevertheless, the power of the House of Commons is not to be underestimated and comfort can be placed in the minds of the members.  It was suggested at the time of the 1911 Parliament Act that the referendum could be employed to resolve conflicts between the two houses of parliament rather than a removal of the LordsÕ power of veto[109].  It was further suggested that the referendum was a necessity only when the absolute veto of the Lords was dying, but not before.[110]  That time has come Ð the House of LordsÕ veto is dead and buried.

 

Indeed, the only remaining constitutional safeguards are the three committees of the House of Commons which scrutinise bills for their adherence to constitutional and legal values,[111] but they have no power to block legislation[112].  Any real constitutional safeguards have been weathered away.[113]

 

There is a demonstrable need for a check on the power of the government. DiceyÕs suspicion that constitutional changes would be enacted without the peopleÕs consent[114] is more relevant as the constitutionÕs constraints on the legislature weaken.  He wrote that checks were necessary Òin order to guard the rights of the nation against the usurpation of national authority by any party which happens to have a parliamentary majority.Ó[115]

 

A democracy is Ògovernment of all the people, by all the people, for all the people.Ó[116]  Referendums strengthen representative democracy by allowing popular participation without necessarily undermining the system of representative government.[117] A stronger democracy is surely preferable. The referendum should also help the fight against the current rising tide of voter apathy and ensure that politicians do not Ôlose touchÕ[118] with the preferences of the electorate.[119]

 

There is huge popular support for referendums.  A 1968 poll found that 69% of respondents believed that Britain should adopt a referendum system and the 1995 MORI/Joseph Rowntree Reform Trust Survey showed that this belief has strengthened with 77% of respondents coming out in favour of the greater use of referendums.Ó[120]  Referendums isolate questions and focus minds.[121] From 50,000 people recently surveyed regarding the European Constitutional Treaty, 70% were in favour of a referendum before ratification.[122]

 

Theoretically the referendum device provides a mechanism of entrenchment like no other.[123]  Currently this entrenchment is political only Ð it has no legal qualities whatsoever.  This is insufficient.

 

5.1.2.        Dismissal of the Case Against

 

All previous serious calls for referenda have allegedly Òfoundered on the difficulty (and, in the view of some, the undesirability) of distinguishing constitutional from ordinary legislation without a written constitution.Ó[124]  Nevertheless many referendums have taken place despite this difficulty Ð this is no longer a valid objection to the referendum, it is a problem to be overcome and a solution is proffered below. Referendums are, however, victims to other difficulties.  But all these difficulties can be minimised such that they longer challenge the referendum as a constitutional device and, more importantly, a constitutional safeguard.

 

The case for referendums is considerably stronger than the case against.  That Òthe mass of the English people are politically contented as well as politically deferentialÓ[125] is no reason to reject direct democracy, indeed it is a reason to advocate it. Solon was asked whether he had given the Athenians the best system of laws.  He replied, ÒNo, only the best they were capable of receivingÓ[126] Ð we are now capable of receiving more than referential party politics.

 

Bogdanor notes that whilst referendums can articulate a submerged consensus, they cannot create it.[127]  But whilst the object of democracy[128] is the debate[129], at some point crucial controversial and difficult decisions will have to be taken, and it is these situations in which the referendum shines. He notes that Òacceptance of the referendum is but the logical consequence of accepting the democratic form of governmentÓ[130]  Some commentators go further:  The Economist claims that Òmost objections to direct democracy are, when you look closely, objections to democracy.Ó[131] 

 

We must remember, however, that the referendum is not perfect.  Nothing is.  The use of referendums as mechanisms of entrenchment is problematic insofar as the cost of protection from unwarranted innovation is a loss of flexibility. The benefits here far outweigh the costs.

 

Bogdanor writes, Òwhere it is known that an unpopular government is committed to a particular outcome, voters may well wish to punish the government even at the cost of defeating a policy which they support.Ó[132] The reverse is also true. Referendum results may reflect the popularity of the current government rather than the nationÕs opinion on the question put to them.[133] But referendums are preferable Ð general elections should not be decided simply on one issue, but on a whole range of criteria.

 

Some argue that direct democracy allows the majority to trample the rights of the minority: CitizensÕ Initiatives have targeted minority groups, for example, quarantining AIDS victims[134] and repealing rights granted to homosexuals in several American states.[135]  Joseph Schumpeter gives examples of (near)-democracies which have persecuted Jews and burnt witches.[136]  Representatives are seemingly more likely to protect minorities.[137]   Referendums have also been criticised because they have been used by authoritarian rulers to justify and legitimise their policies.[138] Qvortrup writes Òa balanced conclusion seems to be this: the referendum is neither better nor worse than representative democracy [at protecting minoritiesÕ rights].Ó [139]  Both direct and representative institutions of democracy can be used to enact legislation that discriminates against minorities.[140]  The Referendum cannot be criticised on this ground Ð it is the place of constitutional courts and Bills of Rights to protect vulnerable minorities who will always require special protection.  To accept this criticism would be to accept that the people, as the sovereign, require protection from themselves.

 

It has been suggested that Ôby providing a politically acceptable way in which elected representatives can evade difficult decisions by passing the buck to voters, referendums make it easy for representatives to shirk their responsibilities and evade the consequences of doing their jobsÕ[141].   Tristan (now Lord) Garel-Jones dubbed it Òan abdication of responsibility.Ó[142]  Referendums do weaken the essential fabric of representative government[143] by reducing its prestige and honour[144] and  Òenabling a government to blame the voters if a policy that was submitted to a referendum turns out to be mistaken or unpopular.Ó[145] But given the benefits outlined above, this is small price to pay.  Furthermore referendums legitimate controversial policy decisions[146] and rarely upset party systems.[147]  Indeed Òthe very concept of Ôrepresentative democracyÕ has been losing ground because the parties favour voting methods that reduce voters to party supporters. Rather than people, who might aspire to have wishes of their own to be represented.Ó[148]

 

Butler and Ranney note that ordinary citizens have neither the analytical skills nor the information to make wise decisions, whilst elected officials can weigh the intensity of opinions and reach compromises.[149] Ian Budge claims that ÒReferendums sometimes stimulate a temporary influx of ill-informed and normally apathetic electors whose participation adds further unpredictability to the result and introduces greater inconsistency and incoherence to the process of decision making.Ó[150]  This analysis is pessimistic, voters are considerably better educated and reasoned at referendum polls than one might at first imagine; indeed it is environments with limited political participation that breed popular ignorance and political complacency.

 

Referendums do not prima-facie Òallow for prudent compromiseÓ[151]: it is the bill, the whole bill, and nothing but the bill.  David Magelby asserts that Òdirect legislation serves to intensify conflict and lead to a politics of confrontation.  In contrast, indirect democracy is generally structured to facilitate compromise, moderation and a degree of access of all segments of the community.Ó[152]  But the nation would not necessarily be divided and polarised if a referendum question was particularly complex or controversial.[153]  Evidence shows that the 1975 referendum gave rise to meaningful intellectual discussion in the media and amongst the people that transcended party lines.[154]  Moreover, a referendum device offering the opportunity to measure the intensity of opinion is available.[155]  In short, the empirical evidence disproves claims that direct democracy is inimical to a system of government which facilitates compromises,[156] and clearly shows that the elite theoristsÕ denunciations of referendums have been greatly premature. 

 

5.2.          The Feasibility of Referendums

 

Referendums are constitutional and desirable but will be inappropriate, unfeasible and illegitimate unless Ôfair playÕ can be ensured.[157]  The losing side must feel that the fight was fairly conducted.[158] All democratic institutions should meet three criteria: equal participation, enlightened participation and minority protection.  Until the referendum can meet this test, its authority will be questionable.

 

Most of the problems examined below are practical, and unlike the metaphysical constitutional problems above, these can be solved by applying a little common sense.

 

5.2.1.        Sovereign Subjects

 

Voters will almost undoubtedly take other matters into account.[159]  But the human mind is not infallible and MPs must suffer the same frailties. There is evidence that voters view referendums as a general election on one issue[160] and may use the opportunity to punish the government Òeven at the cost of defeating a policy which they supported.Ó[161]  However according to Butler and Ranney,  Òreferendum votersÉseem nevertheless to be better informed and more sophisticated than voters in candidate elections.Ó[162]  Recent evidence points to voters being more conscientious than Dicey gave them credit for.[163]   VotersÕ minds focus on the proposed change at General Elections,[164] where everyone realises the importance of the decision to be made.   It is patronising to assume Ð after having accepted popular sovereignty Ð that the People are not capable of making important decisions for themselves.

 

In short, the arguments against entrusting important decisions to the voters are fallacious: the voters are sovereign Ð the decisions are theirs to take.  Whilst decision-making may Ð and in many cases should Ð be delegated to a parliamentary body, that body must always remember the source of its authority and its responsibility to it.

 

5.2.2.        Voting Systems and Majorities

 

Democracy is Greek for Ôrule of the PeopleÕ.[165]  Yet since the People are rarely unanimous a better translation would be rule by the majority.[166] The voting system and the majority used are of paramount importance if a referendumÕs binding force is to be universally accepted.  Currently Òa simple majority of those who cast their votes carries a natural majority.Ó[167] The Labour government insists this is sufficient for devolution.[168]  And whilst Scottish advocates of devolution complained that they were cheated by the 40% rule in 1979, the result was accepted with little resentment.[169]

 

Brazier asks, what would happen if the MPs show a clear majority in one direction and the electorate show a clear majority in the other direction[170] Ð one must overrule the other but which is it to be?  In this case, the decision of the People must carry more constitutional weight than the decision of their elected representatives, provided that the voting system demonstrates equal participation, enlightened participation and minority protection.

 

A qualified or double majority[171] would protect minority rights[172] and entrench legislation, but would be inflexible; whilst a simple majority would facilitate flexibility at the cost of not entrenching rights and rendering the constitution vulnerable to a passing majority.  Despite this fact no country seems to have used a double threshold.[173]  Vernon BogdanorÕs and the Commission on the Conduct of ReferendumsÕ suggestion is to be preferred:  Òif a threshold is used, it should be a set percentage of the votes cast and not a percentage of the eligible electorateÓ[174] Òbecause of possible disputes in calculating the total electorate after making deductions for transient voters and those unable to vote at any given moment.Ó[175]

 

The voting system itself is also important, internationally majorities have taken various different forms.  In Weimar Germany a yes vote from 50% of the population was essential for the referendum to pass Ð if someone abstained, they were counted as a ÔnoÕ.[176]  ÒThere is no reason to suppose the single transferable vote isnÕt equally applicable to referendums, as to representations...STV gives ordinary voters the power of the initiative simply by entering a polling booth, without all the extra constitutional machinery and collective action required for formal initiatives.Ó[177]  Whilst the setting of the majority and threshold is a political decision, STV allows the most comprehensive survey of public opinion.[178]

 

5.2.3.        The Timing of the Vote

 

When should the referendum be held?  And who should decide? Referendums will not become well-respected constitutional safeguards while parliament still decides when and how they are held, as the device remains vulnerable to exploitation from the government.[179]  A date should be set by consensus between political parties or, preferably, by an independent body.  It is submitted, however, that where possible referendums are held at the same time as general elections,[180] this should allay fears of voter fatigue, prevent electors voting down a referendum proposal to punish the government and increase the turnout at the General Elections themselves.[181]

 

Where certainty or an extra degree of entrenchment is desirable, a two-stage process should be applied: the measure should be voted for in two referendums at different times.[182]  This system is particularly suited to situations where the voters have to indicate a preference at the first ballot.  On the second paper the voters could be asked whether they would like to preserve the status quo or whether they support the option put forward in the first referendum.

 

Furthermore, a referendum should not be rushed.  Sufficient time should be allowed for the voters to educate themselves about the question at hand.

 

5.2.4.        The Question to be Put

 

Where, as in Northern Ireland, the protagonists disagree about the definition of the issue, let alone the question, an attempt to hold a referendum may well prove futile.

 

Cronin notes that Òthe greatest deficiency of the referendum is its tendency to force voters to chose between only two alternatives, they must ether approve or reject the measure referred.Ó[183] Questions should allow citizens the opportunity to express the strength of their opinions.[184]   The Commission on the Conduct of referendums recommended that this should Òdepend on the nature of the issue (or issues) to be put to the electorate.Ó[185]  The problem with multi-choice referendums[186] is that they often produce no clear ÔwinnerÕ and evidence from Sweden shows that multi-choice referendums sometimes prolong the issue for much longer than a simple yes-no vote.[187] A system of preference voting would produce clear results and allow supporters of reform to indicate whether they would be prepared to accept their second, or even third, choice reform options over the status quo[188] and allow for prudent compromises.[189]

 

Dawn Oliver asks who should be responsible for writing the question?[190]  Currently the Electoral Commission gives opinions on the intelligibility of questions[191] but does not write them.  Magleby criticises some American states for placing detailed legislation in front of its voters and advocates questions worded in a general, simple and clear manner.[192]  In any event, questions Òshould be short and simple and should not be open to either legal or political challenge after the result is known.Ó[193]  Questions should in fact be written by the commission to prevent bias and safeguards against tendentious questions should be implemented.[194]  In terms of Britain voting to enter the euro, a simple ÔinÕ or ÔoutÕ would serve the same purpose.  Nonetheless, whilst the 1975 referendum shows how delicate the issue of wording can be, it also shows Òhow little difference it can make in the long run.Ó[195]

 

5.2.5.        Money Matters

 

Cronin suggests that Òmoney is, other things being equal, the single most important factor determining direct legislation outcomesÓ[196] yet the government remains concerned that in limiting the spending on referendal campaigns, it is inhibiting freedom of speech.  But, in a society where money Ð quite literally Ð speaks, should those who can afford the biggest media campaigns be allowed to influence voting?  Analysis of past referendums is not comforting. The committee on standards in public life was Ôdisturbed, in particular, by the evidence É that the referendum campaign in Wales in 1997 was very one-sided, with the last-minute ÔNoÕ organisation seriously under-funded and having to rely on financial support essentially on a single wealthy donor.Õ[197]  Thankfully the PPERA[198] imposed restrictions on campaign funding, with the government issuing Ôcore fundingÕ to the main participants and limiting overall spending.  That relief is short-lived. The legislation is flawed.

 

 In the Preface to the White Paper ÔReferendum on United Kingdom Membership of the European CommunityÕ[199] the then government was Òconvinced that any attempt to limit total expenditure by the two sides was impracticable, not least because it could apply only after legislation had received the Royal Assent, and that it would limit traditional freedom of speechÓ[200] The Committee on Standards in Public Life believed that Òit would be futile and possibly also wrong to impose such [spending] limits in connection with referendums.  Ordinary election campaigns bear resemblance to sporting contests, in the sense that they are fought by competing ÔteamsÕ in the form of political partiesÉBy contrast, a referendum campaign is more like a free-for-all.  Anyone can participate.  Many do.Ó[201]  Under these circumstances they claimed that it would be impracticable to try to control campaign spending.  The government did believe that it was in the public interest for information about money spent by major individuals and organisations (and the source of this money) to be disclosed after the event.[202] Why this is so is unclear, once the vote has been counted and the decision taken of what effect is this information if could not be used to prevent a rerun of the same situation in the event of another referendum on the same issue? {Ed.: sentence should be clarified.}

 

Sam Younger, the chairman of the Electional Commission warned in an interview with the times that Òlegislation governing campaign spending was ÔflawedÕ and Ôunworkable.ÕÓ[203]  He claims that Òwealthy organisations on both sides could exploit legal loopholes and hijack the campaign.Ó[204] One of the major problems being that the amount spent can only be analysed after the event, once the result has already been declared.  Neil OÕBrien[205] plans to challenge the government in the courts regarding the funding rules. He claims that the PPERA gives the government Òan unfair advantageÓ[206] since Òthe spending of the ÔyesÕ and ÔnoÕ campaigns is limited by the PPERA for up to six months before a referendum, but the governmentÕs own spending is not limited until the last 28 days of a referendum campaign.Ó[207]  Furthermore one individual could create several different groups, each able to spend £500,000 and thus distort the whole campaign.

 

It appears to be the case is that any legislation, however altruistic its aims, which attempts to limit the spending of referendum campaign groups will be rendered ineffective because such spending will be impossible to police.  Comfort can however be taken from that fact that of the 189 state referendums in the USA between 1976 and 1984 for which spending data is available,[208] Òcampaign spending can be judged the decisive factor in only 23 Ð one eighth of the total.Ó[209]

 

5.2.6.        The influence of Mass Media

 

At election time broadcasters are obliged to be unbiased and neutral in their reporting and grant all parties the opportunity to air their views.  It is submitted that political expedience reduces the amount voters are influenced by the media and the likelihood that (late deciding) participants will vote contrary to their ideological predispositions.[210]  Political awareness also has a moderating effect; Òit decreases the likelihood that partisans will be pulled by a campaign towards decisions deviating from their predispositions and not in like with the campaigns of ÔtheirÕ elite.  It also reduces the likelihood that (late deciding) partisans will vote contrary to their ideological predispositions.Ó[211]

 

Birch also cites numerous studies in the United States to conclude the mass media plays an insignificant part in changing opinions during campaigns, Òpeople exposed themselves mainly to communications with which they were predisposed to agree andÉ they tended the remember the content only of those items with which they had agreed.Ó[212]  It is when the issues are new that Òpredispositions may give voters little guidance, thus enabling campaigns to influence different types of voters more evenly.Ó[213]  In all situations, however a Ôbetter safe than sorryÕ attitude is deemed preferable and such a position is reflected in the PPERA[214].  In any event, the influence of mass media is not to be exaggerated, studies suggest that while mass media may reinforce some peopleÕs opinions, it rarely changes them.[215]

 

5.2.7.        Political Influence

 

Before General Elections politicians are expected to campaign along party lines.  But what is expected of them before a referendum when the major parties may not be competing against each other, and may not even stand united?[216]  If governments decide to hold referendums on questions on which they are themselves divided and formally suspend collective responsibility[217], these divisions will manifest themselves in public speeches and campaigns.[218]   The Committee on Standards in Public LifeÕs recommendation is to be preferred: Òthe government of the day in future referendums should, as a government, remain neutral and should not distribute at public expense literature, even purportedly ÔfactualÕ literature, setting out or otherwise promoting its case.Ó[219]

 

5.3.          Does Direct Democracy Always Lead to Good Decision-Making?

 

Referendums do not provide final solutions.[220]  The referendums on the EC and devolution have not finally resolve the issues.[221]  It has even been argued that referendums weaken representative government by discouraging energetic and innovative leaders from seeking election as legislators, and that the process of compromise and amendments to legislation that improves the quality of the law diminishes with the move towards popular sovereignty and direct democracy. 

 

Referendums have not always led to good decision-making. The Swiss vetoed legislation on national health insurance against their own best interests allegedly under the influence of advertising paid for by the private insurance companies.[222]  States such as Switzerland and California, which make extensive use of the referendum, do suffer difficulties.  Their ability to persue coherent policies is weakened as political parties have a less important role; voters can get fatigued or find themselves unequipped to decide complicated issues and instead rely on their favourite politician or media source to guide them and referendums may be seen as a general election on the government generally.[223]  Furthermore referendums can be used by political parties as publicity devices.  Nevertheless, voters in these states value the referendum and are reluctant to discard it.[224]   Whilst Cronin claims that there is an abundance of evidence that electors are restrained and arrive at the polls well reasoned,[225] Butler notes that referendums can Òconfirm the worst fears of critics and opponents of direct democracy.  Decisions would often be inconsistent with each other and ill considered.  One alternative would be carried on a great wave of emotion at one point, only to be partially abrogated or contradicted in another measure months later.Ó[226]

 

Despite the above criticisms, Zimmerman notes that Òevidence is lacking that the mandatory referendum in general has resulted in poor-quality decisions or that the protest referendum has been abused by special interest groupsÓ[227].  No system of government is prefect and all are open to abuse, a body of elected members in a representative government could very easy pass legislation to persecute minorities, and trample on fundamental human rights[228]. Direct democracy will provide a better system of government, it will not solve all the problems with democracy.

 

5.4.          Direct Democracy in its Most Suitable Form

 

Direct democracy has been proved to be constitutional, desirable and feasible for use in the United Kingdom.  What form it should take is detailed below.

 

ÒAcross the worldÓ, notes Ian Budge, Òthe nearest approach to direct democracy É is where legislative votes are supplemented by referendums or popular initiatives on particular issues, supported by a right of recall of legislation or of elected officials.Ó[229]

 

Direct democracy should undoubtedly embrace the electronic age,[230]  but whilst the most extreme believers in direct democracy advocate using Ònew electronic mass forums to by-pass self-serving legislaturesÓ[231]  it is submitted that the referendum is employed to complement and occasionally correct representative government rather than to replace it.[232]

 

5.4.1.        The Most Appropriate Form of Referendum

 

It is important to recognise the limits on direct democracy.  ÒThe referendum cannotÓ, as Bogdanor has noted, Òdo much to Ôunite a fundamentally divided society.Ó[233]  The Referendum should not, for all its shortcomings, replace representative democracy.[234]  Referenda should not be used for all decision-making.  Highly complex decisions (for example regarding economic policy) are out of reach for most electors.  Others are so mundane that to refer them to the people would be futile.    Indeed Rodney Brazier suggests that there is no case for referendums on any issue other than constitutional change. Other methods of consultation exist to ensure that interested parties can comment on legislation.  This is consistent with Bruce AckermanÕs dualist constitutional system.[235]  Furthermore the referendum should not be over-used so as to become stale and disrespected.  If used sparingly, it Òcan be a tremendous symbolic and significant political tool.Ó[236]

 

MagelbyÕs suggestion that Òsince Britain has an elastic constitution, so the use of the referendum must be elasticÓ[237] is to be rejected.  The ÔelasticÕ use of a referendum does not ensure that the constitution is entrenched, nor is it consistent with popular sovereignty. Referendums should be triggered by citizensÕ initiatives or automatically when significant constitutional change is proposed.[238]  In all events the bar should be set sufficiently high so that the prestige of both parliament and the device itself stays intact.  This could be achieved in a number of different ways. 

 

A list of Ôconstitutional statutesÕ[239] could be maintained and the referendal mechanism triggered if a Bill read in parliament impliedly or explicitly repealed any part of them.  In such a case, the BillÕs progress through the House would be paused until the people could ratify the change at a referendum.  Whilst this would ensure the entrenchment of constitutional statues, several problems are envisaged.  Firstly a constitutional statute is notoriously hard to define.[240] Any Act already referred to the people would no doubt qualify, but this would not include, for example, the Human Rights Act.  A better option would be to entrust a commission to draw up a list of constitutional statutes to date to ensure the inclusion of all relevant statutes.  But this would not solve the problem Ð there is simply no concrete definition of what is or is not constitutional.  Secondly, to enact the Ôenabling actÕ Ð that is the legislation to entrench the automatic process Ð would require parliament to bind itself as to the future.  This is currently constitutionally impossible and would require the legal recognition of the people as the legal sovereign as advocated earlier. 

 

An alternative would be to require the Constitutional Committee of the House of Lords or a new Constitutional Commission[241] to monitor acts in their passage through parliament and recommend a referendum as appropriate.  Whilst this solves the problems of the earlier approach it does not provide an entrenched automatic referendum mechanism as the decision to hold one is still discretional and parliament is not bound for the future.

 

It is submitted that a broadly drafted written constitution that recognises the peopleÕs sovereignty in law is the only watertight solution. As the one immutable, irrefutable and supreme source of law, a referendum would be required before any changes could be made to it.  Either the reading in parliament of a Bill proposing a constitutional amendment or a citizensÕ initiative would trigger such a referendum. There are, however, no plans for a written constitution in the UK. 

 

Furthermore any automatic trigger scheme seems unlikely.  Nick Raynsford, the UK Local Government Minister suggested that a fixed formula by which to trigger referenda would be ÒunrealisticÓ[242].  This is a disappointing statement and a setback for direct democracy campaigners in the UK.

 

5.4.2.        The Most Appropriate Form of CitizensÕ Initiative

 

Bogdanor importantly notes, Òalthough commonly seen as an instrument of popular sovereignty, the constitutional referendum gives the people only the power of veto.  The electorate is confined to giving a verdict on a change that has already been endorsed.Ó[243]  Thus, limited use of the initiative should be also be employed, to allow the electorate to propose legislation or referendums directly.

 

The risk is that the citizensÕ initiatives will be abused by well-funded groups to advance their cause[244].  Indeed in California an industry has sprung up which is dedicated to finding funding for initiative campaigns.  And ever since the Supreme Court struck down state legislation imposing caps on referendum spending the possibility that the referenda may be Ôhigh jackedÕ by rich individuals or corporations has increased.[245]  It is important that there is no such room for abuse in any British initiative process, and that the initiative is not used spuriously.  It is submitted that the quorum required before the initiative be declared valid be set very high so as to discourage all but the most pressing issues.[246]

 

The CitizensÕ Initiative and Referendum Campaign proposes a three-step procedure: (1) An initiative which can lead to the debate of the proposal by parliament.  If the proposal is rejected by parliament, and a required number of endorsements are collected from citizens then: (2) PeopleÕs referendum demand.  (3) A referendum must be held on the topic. The decision of the referendum is legally binding.[247]  They claim that this will create an Òideas greenhouseÓ where progressive policies will be cultivated by the people, yet the required number of endorsements should not be set so low as to render it frivolous.  Furthermore the proposed system Òintegrates parliamentary and citizensÕ democracy.  It brings citizens and MPs together to consider and debate issues of real concern to the electorate.  Negotiation often occurs.Ó

 

 

6.  CONCLUSIONS

 

 

The referendum is more popular in the UK than ever before.  ÒConsciously or unconsciously, through the use of referendums Tony Blair has completely changed the constitutional landscape in this country.Ó[248]  It is compatible with parliamentary sovereignty insofar as parliament may refer questions to the people and there is a strong case to suggest that a referendal convention has arisen.  But this is insufficient.

 

At law the referendum lacks binding force, it remains an opinion poll.  Furthermore, the People have no right to be consulted when constitutional amendments are made. There is no legal requirement for referendums to be held.  It has been shown that if the people are accorded their proper position in law Ð that of the sovereign Ð then the referendum would become a key pillar of the constitution.  Simply put, embracing the referendum will result in a better form of democracy.

 

Unfortunately the legal recognition of popular sovereignty would require the rejection of parliamentary sovereignty. This in itself is legally impossible as parliament is unable to bind itself to the future.  In law the two are incompatible.  A self-denying ordinance would only be valid insofar as it was not subjected to implied or explicit repeal.  It would appear that there is no solution.

 

However Wade writes that ÒDicey had no doubt that the abdication of sovereignty, whether total or partial, was consistent with his conception of parliamentary sovereignty.  He argued that a sovereign power could divest itself of authority in two ways only, by outing an end to its own existence and leaving no means whereby a subsequent parliament could be legally summoned or by transferring sovereign power wholly or in part to a sovereign body.Ó[249] A written constitution recognising popular sovereignty, approved by all electors at a referendum would have indisputable legal force.  It need not even be a parliamentary self-denying ordinance, nor an ÔordinaryÕ Bill requiring royal assent as Dicey implies.  It should be considered a social contract between the people.  This would entrench popular sovereignty in law, giving binding force to the referendum and maintain the House of Commons as the primary law-making body. ÒIn the absence of a codified constitution, a referendum cannot ever be required as an instrument to ratify legislation.Ó[250]

 

A written constitution would also solve a greater problem, namely: what is the constitution?  We currently let the tail wag the dog Ð a statuteÕs constitutional status is confirmed when it is submitted to the people at a referendum, it is not submitted because of its confirmed constitutional status.

 

Unfortunately there are no plans for a written constitution and a revolution is highly unlikely.  Therefore one must, for the time being, advocate an intermediary solution and rely on the consciences of not only MPs, but their party leaders over whom we have diminishing control and in the fact that the House of Commons is subject to regular General Elections.  A standing commission should be established and a list of constitutional statutes maintained as suggested above.  Furthermore, provisions should be made to enable the citizens to propose legislation or referendums directly by means of a CitizensÕ Initiative regardless of their strict legal status.

 

Whilst there are solutions to the practical problems with such mechanisms, safeguards must be put in place to ensure that the process is fair and leads to good decision-making.  The PPERA 2000 clearly requires amendment. 





7.  APPENDICES

7.1.          Table of Major Referendums in the UK

 

NAME

DATE

QUESTION

RESULT

Northern Ireland Referendum

1973

On whether NI should remain part of the UK

Yes

United Kingdom Referendum

1975

On whether the UK should remain part of the European Community

YES

Scotland Referendum

1979

On whether there should be a Scottish Parliament

NO

Wales Referendum

1979

On whether there should be a welsh assembly

NO

Scotland Referendum

1997

Two questions:

1)    on whether there should be a Scottish Parliament

2)    on whether a Scottish Parliament should have tax varying powers

 

YES

 

YES

Wales Referendum

1997

On whether there should be a Welsh Assembly

YES

London Referendum

1998

On whether there should be a Mayor of London and Greater London Authority

YES

Northern Ireland Referendum

1998

On the Good Friday Agreement

YES

North East referendum

2004

On elected regional assembly

NO

North West referendum

[Tabled]

On elected regional assembly

 

Yorkshire referendum

[Tabled]

On elected regional assembly

 

UK Referendum on the EU constitution

Expected 2006

On the adoption/ratification of the EU constitution

 

Euro Referendum

 

On the adoption of the Euro

 

Referendum on voting system for the House of Commons

 

To chose a method of electing members of parliament

 

Source = Anon, http://www.thebestlinks.com/Referendums_in_the_United_Kingdom.html


8.  BIBLIOGRAPHY

8.1.          Books

 

  • Akerman, Bruce We the People: Transformations (Cambridge, Mass. 1998) Vol II
  • Bagehot, W and Crossman, H R S (eds) , The English Constitution (C A Watts & CO Ltd, 1964)
  • Bagehot, W The English Constitution, (Fontana, London 1963)
  • Birch, A H Representative and responsible Government (George Allen and Unwin Ltd, 1964)
  • Blackstone, Sir William Commentaries III 17
  • Bogdanor, Vernon The People and the Party System.  The Referendum and Elected reform in British Politics (CUP, Cambridge, 1981)
  • Bogdanor, Vernon Power and the People, A Guide of Constitutional Reform (Victor Gollancz
  • Bowler, Shaun, Donovan, Todd and Tolbert, Caroline J (eds) Citizens as Legislators Ð Direct Democracy in the United States (Ohio State University Press, Columbus, 1998)
  • Brazier Rodney (ed), Stanley de Smith and Rodney Brazier, Constitutional and Administrative Law (8th ed, Penguin Books, London 1998)
  • Brazier, Rodney Constitutional Reform (2nd ed., Oxford 1998)
  • Budge, Ian The New Challenge of Direct Democracy (Blackwell, 1996)
  • Butler, David and Ranney, Austin (eds) Referendums Around the World Ð The Growing Use of Direct Democracy (Macmillan, London, 1994)
  • Butler David and Ranney, Austin Referendums.  A Comparative Study of Practice and Theory (American Enterprise Institute, Washington DC, 1978)
  • Butler, David and Kitzinger, Uwe The 1975 Referendum (Macmillan Press, London, 1976)
  • Charter 88, Reinventing Voting Ð holding a referendum of elections to the commons, (Charter 88, London, 1996)
  • Constitution Unit Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit, Faculty of Laws, University College London, 1996)
  • Cronin, Direct Democracy, the Politics of Initiative, Referendum and Recall (Harvard University Press, 1989)
  • Dicey, A V Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (12th ed. Macmillan & Co. Ltd, London, 1959)
  • Dicey, A V Lectures on the Relation Between Law & Public Opinion in England during the nineteenth century (2nd ed, Macmillan, London, 1930)
  • Dicey, A V Ought the Referendum to be Introduced into England (Contemporary Review, 1890)
  • Farrell, David M and Schmitt-Beck, Rudiger (eds) Do Political Campaigns Matter? Ð campaign effects in elections and referendums (Routledge, ECPR studies in European Political Sciences, 2002) p191
  • Gibbon, Edward The History of the Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire
  • Hardy, Thomas The Hand of the Etherlberta [1876]
  • Harper, Ross J Referendums are Dangerous (Conservate Political Centre, London, 1997)
  • Haskell, John Direct Democracy or Representative Government Ð dispelling the populist Myth (Westview Press, Oxford, 2001)
  • Kaplan, Justin (ed) & Bartlett, John BartlettÕs Familiar Quotations (17th ed, Boston, Little, Brown and Company)
  • Killick, Anna and Puddephatt, Andrew Reinventing voting Ð Holding a referendum on elections to the Commons (Charter 88, London, 1996)
  • Lijphart, Arend Democracies.  Patterns of Majoritarian and Consensus Government in Twenty-One Countruies (Yale University Press, New Haven, 1984) p 203
  • Lock, John Second Treatise of Government
  • Magelby, David B Direct Legislation.  Voting on Ballot propositions in the United States (Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press, 1984)
  • Mendelsohn, Matthew and Parkin, Andrew (eds) Referendum Democracy Ð Citizens, Elites and Deliberation in Referendum Campaigns (Palgrave, London, 2001)
  • McLean, Iaian The Concise Dictionary of Politics (OUP, Oxford, 1996)
  • Menicus, Works III
  • Michels, Robert Political Parties Ð A Sociological study of the Oligarchical Tendencies of Modern Democracy (The Free Press, New York, 1968)
  • Oliver, Dawn Constitutional Reform in the UK (Oxford University Press, 2003)
  • Plato, Republic
  • Qvortrup, Mads A Comparative Study of Referendums Ð Government by the People (Manchester University Press, Manchester, 2002)
  • Ranney, Ausitn (ed) The Referendum Device (Washington DC: American Enterprise Instutute, 1981)
  • Roche, Julian No Referenda  Please Ð WeÕre British (The Bow Group, London, 1995)
  • Schmidt, Citizen Lawmakers (Temple University Press, Philadelphia, 1989)
  • Suksi, Markku Bringing in the People, A comparison of Constitutional Forms and Practices of the Referendum (Martinus Nijhoft publishers, 1993)
  • Zimmerman, Joseph F Participatory Democracy Ð Populism Revived (Praeger Publishers, 1986)

 

8.2.          Articles

 

  • Bogdanor, Vernon Our New Constitution [2004] LQR 120
  • Brazier, The Constitution of the UK [1999] CLJ 96-128
  • Frank, Hans Volkischer Beobahter [May 20, 1936]
  • Hazel, Robert Who is the Guardian of Legal values in the Legislative Process: Parliament or the Executive? [2004] PL 495
  • Magelby, David Taking the initiative: Direct Legislation and Direct Democracy in the 1980sÕ Political Science and Politics, 21  3 Summer [1988] 608
  • Weil, Rivka We the British People [2004] PL 380
  • Weil, Rivka Dicey was not Diceyan (CLJ [2003] 474)
  • Wade, H W R The Basis of Legal Sovereignty [1955] CLJ 172
  • The Times, Councils to be pruned as ministers absorb lessons of referendums rebuff (1/1/2005)

 

8.3.          Official Publications

 

  • Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996)
  • Committee on Standards in Public Life, Fifth Report Standards in Public Life; the funding of Political Parties in the United Kingdom
  • Constitution Committee, First Report, Reviewing the Constitution (2001 Ð 02 HL 11)
  • Constitution Unit, Delivering Constitutional Reform (Constitution Unit, Faculty of Laws, University College London)
  • Local Government Association, Local referendums and citizensÕ ballots (Local Government Association, London, 2001)
  • Taming the Prerogative: Strengthening Ministerial Accountability to Parliament (2003-04 HC 422)
  • The 5th report of the Committee on Standards in Public Life, The Funding of Political Parties (Cm. 4057 (1998))
  • The Institute of Welsh Affairs, The Road to the Referendum Requirements for a Fair Debate (Institute of Welsh Affairs, 1996) 
  • Referendum on United Kingdom Membership of the European Community, 26 February 1975, Cmnd 5925
  • Canadian Parliamentary Research Branch, Referendums: the Canadian Experience in an International Context (Law and Government Division, 1992) 

 

8.4.          Electronic Resources

 

 

 

8.5.          Cases Referred to

 

  • Ellen Street Estates Ltd v Minister of Health [1934] 1 KB 590

 

8.6.          Statutes Referred to

 

á      Human Rights Act 1998

á      Northern Ireland Act 1998

á      Parliament Act 1911

á      Political Parties, Elections and Referendums Act 2000

 

8.7.          Miscellaneous Resources

 

  • Parker, Theodore The American Idea, speech at the New England Anti Slavery Convention, Boston [May 29, 1850]#
  • Bryce Papers, Bodlein Library, MS 4 to 84
  • Salisbury Papers
  • The Economist, December 1996


9.  REFERENCES


[1] Clement Atlee when responding to whether a referendum be held to extend BritainÕs wartime coalition until JapanÕs surrender.  As per Ollie Stone-Lee, The UK and referendums (BBC Online)

[2] Walter Bagehot, The English Constitution, (Fontana, London, 1963) in Rivka Weil, We the British People [2004] PL 380

[3] Mads Qvortrup, A Comparative Study of Referendums Ð Government by the People (Manchester University Press, Manchester, 2002)

[4] Iaian McLean (eds), The Concise Dictionary of Politics (OUP, Oxford, 1996).

[5] Plebiscite = Latin for Ôordinance of the peopleÕ, resurrected by Voltaire to describe the referendum in Switzerland.  In the 19th century, plebiscite was used in English as a derogatory term to describe referendums called by Napoleon I and Napoleon III to boost their personal authority, but the term is no longer regarded as derogatory.  As per Iaian McLean (eds), The Concise Dictionary of Politics (OUP, Oxford, 1996).

[6] Interestingly Whilst Winston Churchill argued for the issue of female suffrage to be decided by referendum in 1910.

[7] Rodney Brazier, Constitutional Reform (2nd ed., Oxford 1998)

[8] Birch in Vernon Bogdanor Our New Constitution [2004] LQR 120

[9] Constitution Unit, Delivering Constitutional Reform (Constitution Unit, Faculty of Laws, University College London) p66

[10] Prime Minister Harold Wilson quoted by Mads Qvortrup in Vote 2004, BlairÕs referendums www.vote-2004.com

[11] Vernon Bogdanor, Power and the People, A Guide of Constitutional Reform (Victor Gollancz, 1997)

[12] David Butler and Austin Ranney (eds) Referendums Around the World Ð The Growing Use of Direct Democracy (Macmillan, London, 1994) p33.   See also Vernon Bogdanor Our New Constitution [2004] LQR 120, 242

[13] Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996) p22

[14] Vernon Bogdanor, Power and the People, A Guide of Constitutional Reform (Victor Gollancz, 1997) p25

[15] See Appendix A: List of referendums in the United Kingdom

[16] See Fifth Report of the Committee on Standards in Public Life, Standards in Public Life; the funding of Political Parties in the United Kingdom 12.2

[17] Scotland devolution (1997), Wales devolution (1997), Northern Ireland re the Good Friday Agreement (1998) and the Greater London Mayoral Referendum (1998)

[18] Anon, http://www.thebestlinks.com/Referendums_in_the_United_Kingdom.html

[19] This referendum is now unlikely to take place.  The 1997 Labour Manifesto claimed Òwe are committed to a referendum on the voting system for the House of CommonsÓ (http://www.labour-party.org.uk/manifests/1997/1997-labour-manifesto.shtml). There was no such promise in the 2001 manifesto.

[20] Mads Qvortrup in Introduction to Vote 2004, BlairÕs referendums www.vote-2004.com

[21] Nigel Smith was the chair of the all-party yes campaign in the Scottish referendum of 1997

[22] Nigel Smith in Vote 2004, BlairÕs referendums www.vote-2004.com

[23] Constitution Unit, Delivering Constitutional Reform (Constitution Unit, Faculty of Laws, University College London) para 234

[24] Mads Quortrup in Introduction to Vote 2004, BlairÕs referendums www.vote-2004.com

[25] For example the referendums on devolution in Scotland, Wales and the regions and the referendum on the EC.  E C S Wade submits that the sovereignty of parliament is unlimited by the transfer of legislative authority to the EC.  If, for example, the sovereign in the United Kingdom should wish to leave the European Union, then Ð in terms of national constitutional law Ð that could be effected by an ordinary piece of legislation.  Whether there are any international sanctions on so doing does not effect the position in British constitutional law.  E C S Wade in Dicey Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (12th ed. Macmillan & Co. Ltd, London, 1959)

[26] Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996) p18

[27] Nigel Smith in Vote 2004, BlairÕs referendums www.vote-2004.com

[28] Constitution Unit, Delivering Constitutional Reform (Constitution Unit, Faculty of Laws, University College London) para 231

[29] On 17th October 2003 Tony Blair said: Òthere will not be a referendum.Ó In an interview for The Times, he said it would "not be a wise thing" to have the Government "convulsed" for months preparing for a referendum on the issue (BBC News, Tracking BlairÕs EU comments, BBC Online http://news.bbc.co.uk/go/pr/fr/-/1/hi/uk_politics/3638491.stm ) by December of that year his opinion was ÒletÕs wait and seeÓ ( from the Daily Mail: http://www.dailymail.co.uk/pages/live/articles/news/news.html?in_article_id=199505&in_page_id=1770 )  Yet, soon after announcing that his Òpolicy has not changedÓ in April 2004 he conceded a referendum on the very same subject ( BBC News, Tracking BlairÕs EU comments, BBC Online http://news.bbc.co.uk/go/pr/fr/-/1/hi/uk_politics/3638491.stm )

[30] Nigel Smith in Vote 2004, BlairÕs referendums www.vote-2004.com

[31] This is in marked contrast to many other states, where constitutional changes must be authorised by the people Ð e.g. Australia.

[32] The Institute of Welsh Affairs, The Road to the Referendum Requirements for a Fair Debate (Institute of Welsh Affairs, 1996)  in the Fifth Report of the Committee on Standards in Public Life, Standards in Public Life; the funding of Political Parties in the United Kingdom 12.4

[33] David Butler and Austin Ranney (eds) Referendums Around the World Ð The Growing Use of Direct Democracy (Macmillan, London, 1994) p33

[34] Vernon Bogdanor, Power and the People, A Guide of Constitutional Reform (Victor Gollancz, 1997)

[35]   The 5th report of the Committee on Standards in Public Life, The Funding of Political Parties (Cm. 4057 (1998)) Ch 12: Referendums.  Such a regulatory scheme is also advocated by the Constitution Unit, in its Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit, Faculty of Laws, University College London, 1996)

[36] The Institute of Welsh Affairs, The Road to the Referendum Requirements for a Fair Debate (Institute of Welsh Affairs, 1996)  in the Fifth Report of the Committee on Standards in Public Life, Standards in Public Life; the funding of Political Parties in the United Kingdom 12.4

[37] Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996) p22

[38] See Below for the most appropriate type of referendum in Chapter 5(d)I

[40] Dawn Oliver, Constitutional Reform in the UK (Oxford University Press, 2003)

[41] See chapter 4(c) below re a new constitutional convention.

[42] See for example Dawn Oliver, Constitutional Reform in the UK (Oxford University Press, 2003) p155

[43] A V Dicey, Ought the Referendum to be Introduced into England (Contemporary Review, 1890)

[44] Bryce to Dicey, 6th April 1915: Bryce Papers, Bodlein Library, MS 4 to 84, in Vernon Bogdanor at Ch 3 p33, David Butler and Ausin Ranney(eds), Referendums Around the World, The Growing use of Direct Democracy (Macmillan, 1994)

[45] Mads Qvortrup, A Comparative Study of Referendums Ð Government by the People (Manchester University Press, Manchester, 2002) p1

[46] E C S Wade in Dicey Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (12th ed. Macmillan & Co. Ltd, London, 1959)

[47] Ôthere is no marked or clear distinction between laws which are not fundamental and constitutional and laws which are fundamental and constitutionalÕ as per A. V. Dicey, Introduction to the Study of the Constitution (online text at http://constitution.org/cmt/avd/law_conn.htm)

[48] Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996) p22

[49] Constitution Committee, First Report, Reviewing the Constitution (2001 Ð 02 HL 11) Chapter 2

[50] Sir William Blackstone, Commentaries III 17 in Kaplan, Justin (ed) & Bartlett, John BartlettÕs Familiar Quotations (17th ed, Boston, Little, Brown and Company)

[51] A V Dicey, source unknown in Vernon Bogdanor Our New Constitution [2004] LQR 120

[52] A V Dicey, source unknown in Vernon Bogdanor Our New Constitution [2004] LQR 120

[53] ÒSovereignty is often conceived of as the only kind and absolute authority in a community, and, as such, unlimited, one and indivisible, omnipotent, and even infallibleÓ Markku Suksi, Bringing in the People, A comparison of Constitutional Forms and Practices of the Referendum (Martinus Nijhoft publishers, 1993) p15

[54] Rivka Weil, We the British People [2004] PL 380

[55] E C S Wade in Dicey Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (12th ed. Macmillan & Co. Ltd, London, 1959)

[56] Referendal Theory = That the House of Lords was a check on the power of the House of Commons on behalf of the people

[57] Rivka Weil, We the British People [2004] PL 380

[58] Joseph F Zimerman: Participatory Democracy Ð Populism Revived (Praeger Publishers, 1986)

[59] [1934] 1 KB 590

[60] Ellen Street Estates Ltd v Minister of Health [1934] 1 KB 590

[61] Charter 88, Reinventing Voting Ð holding a referendum of elections to the commons, (Charter 88, London, 1996)

[62]  W Bagehot and H R S Crossman (eds) , The English Constitution (C A Watts & CO Ltd, 1964)

[63] Indeed on p 248 he writes ÒThe English constitution in its palpable form is this Ð the mass of the people yield obedience to a select few; and when you see this select few, you perceive that though not of the lowest class, nor of an unrespectable class, they are yet of a heavily sensible class Ð the last people in the world to whom, if they were drawn up in a rowÉwould ever give an exclusive preference.Ó W Bagehot and H R S Crossman (eds) , The English Constitution (C A Watts & CO Ltd, 1964)

[64] Bagehot and H R S Crossman (eds) , The English Constitution (C A Watts & CO Ltd, 1964) p218

[65] E C S Wade in Dicey Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (12th ed. Macmillan & Co. Ltd, London, 1959)

[66] Bagehot and H R S Crossman (eds) , The English Constitution (C A Watts & CO Ltd, 1964) p214

[68] The capitalisation of ÔPeopleÕ Òdescribes the instances in which the people mobilise, deliberate and pronouns their deliberate and sustained opionion on constiutional change. This happens at times when the people engage in public life with the seriousness they usually accord the most important decisions of their private lives.  In all aother times we refer to Ôthe peopleÕ without a capital.  This follows the work of Professor Bruce Ackerman of Yale Law School.  See Bruce Akerman, We the People: Transformations (Cambridge, Mass. 1998) Vol IIÓ in Rivka Weil, Dicey was not Diceyan (CLJ [2003] 575)

[69] Rivka Weil, Dicey was not Diceyan (CLJ [2003] 474)

[70] E C S Wade in Dicey Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (12th ed. Macmillan & Co. Ltd, London, 1959)

[71] Iaian McLean, The Concise Dictionary of Politics (OUP, Oxford, 1996) p130

[72] A V Dicey, Lectures on the Relation Between Law & Public Opinion in England during the nineteenth century (2nd ed, Macmillan, London, 1930) p10

[73] A V Dicey, Lectures on the Relation Between Law & Public Opinion in England during the nineteenth century (Macmillan, London, 1930) p11

[74] Bogdanor in Magleby, Direct Legislation, Voting on Ballot Propositions in the United States (The John Hopkins University Press, 1984) p46

[75] A V Dicey, Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (12th ed. Macmillan & Co. Ltd, London, 1959)

[76] Rivka Weil, Dicey was not Diceyan (CLJ [2003] 474) at 475

[77] Rivka Weil, Dicey was not Diceyan (CLJ [2003] 575)

[78] Rivka Weil, Dicey was not Diceyan (CLJ [2003] 575)

[79] Vernon Bogdanor Our New Constitution [2004] LQR 120

[80] Vernon Bogdanor in Magleby, Direct Legislation, Voting on Ballot Propositions in the United States (The John Hopkins University Press, 1984) p35

[81] A V Dicey, Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (12th ed. Macmillan & Co. Ltd, London, 1959) p423

[82] Vernon Bogdanor, Our New Constitution [2004] LQR 120, 242

[83] Vernon Bogdanor, Our New Constitution [2004] LQR 120, 242

[84] Vernon Bogdanor Our New Constitution [2004] LQR 120, 242

[85] BBC, On this day: 6 June 1975 (BBC online)

[86] Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996) p24

[87] Conservative Party website, Public must decide future of the Welsh Assembly (30/11/2004) http://www.conservatives.com/tile.do?def=news.story.page&obj_id=117763

[88] Kevin Bampton, On-line discussion concerning the legal basis for national referendums in Britain www.iniref.org/natref1.html

[89] Northern Ireland Act 1998 s.1(1),  re-enacting s.1 Northern Ireland (Constitution) Act 1973

[90] Northern Ireland Act 1998 s.2: (2)But if the wish expressed by a majority in such a poll is that Northern Ireland shotild cease to be part of the United Kingdom and form part of a united Ireland, the Secretary of State shall lay before Parliament such proposals to give effect to that wish as may be agreed between Her MajestyÕs Government in the United Kingdom and the Government of Ireland.

[91] Chris Ashton, On-line discussion concerning the legal basis for national referendums in Britain www.iniref.org/natref1.html

[92] Colin Talbot, On-line discussion concerning the legal basis for national referendums in Britain www.iniref.org/natref1.html

[93] Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996)

[94] A M Green, On-line discussion concerning the legal basis for national referendums in Britain www.iniref.org/natref1.html

[95] in Joseph F. Zimmerman, Participatory Democracy Ð Populism Revived (Praeger Publishers, 1986)

[96] Nicholas Aroney writes that Òs.53(1) of the Constitution Act 1867 (Queensland) provides: ÒA Bill that expressly or impliedly provides for the abolition of or alteration in the office of the Governor or that expressly or impliedly in any way affects any of the following sections of this ActÉshall not be presented for assent by or in the name of the Queen unless it has first been approved by the electors in accordance with this sectionÉÓ On-line discussion concerning the legal basis for national referendums in Britain www.iniref.org/natref1.html

[97] Vernon Bogdanor, Our New Constitution [2004] LQR 120

[98] Iaian McLean, The Concise Dictionary of Politics (OUP, Oxford, 1996)

[99] Athenian democracy was direct, all citizens were expected to participate and the sovereign body would consist of up to 6,000 members.  When decision-making took place in smaller groups, the participants were drawn from lots rather than elected by their peers Iaian McLean, The Concise Dictionary of Politics (OUP, Oxford, 1996) p131

[100] Magleby, Direct Legislation, Voting on Ballot Propositions in the United States (The John Hopkins University Press, 1984) p180-181

[101] http://www.iniref.org/direct.or.indirect.html

[102] Rodney Brazier, Constitutional Reform (2nd ed., Oxford 1998) p36

[103] Plato, Republic VIII 558-C in Kaplan, Justin (ed) & Bartlett, John BartlettÕs Familiar Quotations (17th ed, Boston, Little, Brown and Company)

[104] Vernon Bogdanor, Power and the People, A Guide of Constitutional Reform (Victor Gollancz, 1997) p144.  In the early 1960s, Gabrial Almond and Sidny Verba in their classic work, The Civic Culture saw Britain as a paradigm example of a deferential political culture

[105] Richard Lung, When knowledge fails belief: referendums (www.voting.ukscientist.com/referend.htm

[106] Edward Gibbon, The History of the Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire in Kaplan, Justin (ed) & Bartlett, John BartlettÕs Familiar Quotations (17th ed, Boston, Little, Brown and Company): ÒThe principles of a free constitution are irrevocably lost, when the legislative power is dominated by the executive.Ó

[107] Taming the Prerogative: Strengthening Ministerial Accountability to Parliament (2003-04 HC 422)

[108] A V Dicey, Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (12th ed. Macmillan & Co. Ltd, London, 1959)

[109] Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996) p19

[110] Vernon Bogdanor, The People and the Party System.  The Referendum and Elected reform in British Politics (CUP, Cambridge, 1981)

[111] Robert Hazel describes these as Ôthree new pillars of the constitution.Ó  They are the Delegated Power and Regulatory Reform Committee (which guards against ÔenablingÕ or ÔskeletonÕ bills which would simply enable the government to legislate by secondary legislation), the Joint Committee on Human Rights (which reports on bills which risk Human Rights Violations) and the Select Committee on the Constitution (the terms of reference of which are Òto examine the constitutional implications of all public Bills coming before the House; and to keep under review the operation of the constitution)  Robert Hazel, Who is the Guardian of Legal values in the Legislative Process: Parliament or the Executive? [2004] PL 495

[112] The Crown, of course may refuse to give Royal Assent to a Bill but such an act may in itself be unconstitutional.

[113] See previously, regarding the passing of the Parliament Act.

[114] Rivka Weil, Dicey was not Diceyan (CLJ [2003] 575)

[115] Cosgrove, quoting Dicey to Salisbury, 11 November 1892, Salisbury Papers

[116] Theodore Parker, The American Idea, speech at the New England Anti Slavery Convention, Boston [May 29, 1850 in Kaplan, Justin (ed) & Bartlett, John BartlettÕs Familiar Quotations (17th ed, Boston, Little, Brown and Company)

[117] Mads Qvortrup, A Comparative Study of Referendums Ð Government by the People (Manchester University Press, Manchester, 2002) p7

[118] Mads Qvortrup, A Comparative Study of Referendums Ð Government by the People (Manchester University Press, Manchester, 2002)

[119] Iaian McLean, The Concise Dictionary of Politics (OUP, Oxford, 1996)

[120] Constitution Unit, Delivering Constitutional Reform (Constitution Unit, Faculty of Laws, University College London) para 237

[121] Rivka Weil, Dicey was not Diceyan (CLJ [2003] 575)

[122] Michael Macpherson (by email)

[123] This is as a result of precedent and convention.  Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996)

[124] Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996) p22

[125] W Bagehot and H R S Crossman (eds) , The English Constitution (C A Watts & CO Ltd, 1964) p250

[126] Richard Lung, When knowledge fails belief: referendums (www.voting.ukscientist.com/referend.htm

[127] in Dawn Oliver, Constitutional Reform in the UK (Oxford University Press, 2003) p155

[128] Whilst this is not an investigation into the demerits of democracy, it is relevant to note that ÒPlato and Aristotle both deplored democracy, Plato on the grounds that it handed control of the government from experts in governing to populist demagogues and Aristotle on the grounds that government by the people was in practice government by the poor, who could be expected to expropriate the rich.Ó  Iaian McLean, The Concise Dictionary of Politics (OUP, Oxford, 1996)

[129] For further information see Hla Koch, elaborating thomas MasarykÕs theory in Mads Qvortrup, A Comparative Study of Referendums Ð Government by the People (Manchester University Press, Manchester, 2002) p7: ÒThe essence of democracyÉis not the vote but the discussion.  The vote is assuredly an integral part of democratic decision-making.  When the matter has been discussed, then a vote must be taken.  For it is the vote which shows if the discussion has been fruitful. What is undemocratic is the fruitless debate where neither side listens with an open mindÓ

[130] Vernon Bogdanor, The People and the Party System.  The Referendum and Elected reform in British Politics (CUP, Cambridge, 1981) p93

[131] As per The Economist in December 1996 in Mads Qvortrup, A Comparative Study of Referendums Ð Government by the People (Manchester University Press, Manchester, 2002)

[132] Vernon Bogdanor, Power and the People, A Guide of Constitutional Reform (Victor Gollancz, 1997) p132

[133] Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996) p24

[134] David Magelby, Taking the initiative: Direct Legislation and Direct Democracy in the 1980sÕ Political Science and Politics, 21  3 Summer [1988] 608

[135] Derrick Bell, The Referendum p19

[136] Iaian McLean, The Concise Dictionary of Politics (OUP, Oxford, 1996)

[137] Magleby, Direct Legislation, Voting on Ballot Propositions in the United States (The John Hopkins University Press, 1984)

[138] Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996) p24

[139] Mads Qvortrup, A Comparative Study of Referendums Ð Government by the People (Manchester University Press, Manchester, 2002) p14

[140] Mads Qvortrup, A Comparative Study of Referendums Ð Government by the People (Manchester University Press, Manchester, 2002) p14

[141] David Butler & Austin Ranney (eds), Referendums Around the World, The Growing use of Direct Democracy (Macmillan, 1994) p18 p20

[142] Mads Qvortrup in an Introduction to Vote 2004, BlairÕs referendums www.vote-2004.com

[143] Cronin, Direct Democracy, the Politics of Initiative, Referendum and Recall (Harvard University Press, 1989) p183

[144] Magleby, Direct Legislation, Voting on Ballot Propositions in the United States (The John Hopkins University Press, 1984)

[145] Dawn Oliver, Constitutional Reform in the UK (Oxford University Press, 2003)

[146] Dawn Oliver, Constitutional Reform in the UK (Oxford University Press, 2003)

[147] Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996) p18.  the only evidence of an upset party system is in Norway.

[148] Richard Lung, When knowledge fails belief: referendums (www.voting.ukscientist.com/referend.htm

[149] Indeed it has been suggested that the essence of democracy is not the decision but the discussion that led to it.

[150] Ian Budge, The New Challenge of Direct Democracy (Blackwell, 1996) p89

[151] Cronin, Direct Democracy, the Politics of Initiative, Referendum and Recall (Harvard University Press, 1989) p183

[152] David B Magelby, Direct Legislation.  Voting on Ballot propositions in the United States (Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press, 1984) in Mads Qvortrup, A Comparative Study of Referendums Ð Government by the People (Manchester University Press, Manchester, 2002)

[153] Cronin, Direct Democracy, the Politics of Initiative, Referendum and Recall (Harvard University Press, 1989) p183

[154] See Vernon Bogdanor, the people and the party system p84

[155] See later re ÔThe QuestionÕ

[156] Mads Qvortrup, A Comparative Study of Referendums Ð Government by the People (Manchester University Press, Manchester, 2002) 11

[157] The Liberal DemocratsÕ main concern before the 1975 referendum was that it should be decided on a Ôlevel playing fieldÕ  See Fifth Report of the Committee on Standards in Public Life, Standards in Public Life; the funding of Political Parties in the United Kingdom para 12.24

[158] Vernon Bogdanor in See Fifth Report of the Committee on Standards in Public Life, Standards in Public Life; the funding of Political Parties in the United Kingdom 12.4

[159] Rodney Brazier, Constitutional Reform (2nd ed., Oxford 1998) p35

[160] Such as Ireland on the Nice Treaty and SwedenÕs vote on the Single European Currency

[161] Vernon Bogdanor, Power and the People, a Guide to Constitutional Reform (Victor Gollancz, 1997) p132

[162] David Butler & Austin Ranney (eds), Referendums Around the World, The Growing use of Direct Democracy (Macmillan, 1994) p18

[163] Dicey claimed that ÔIn England the introduction of the referendum meansÉthe transfer of political power from knowledge to ignoranceÓ, he went on to say that if referendums had been employed, the vaccination programme would have been stopped and steam engines might have been banned. A. V. Dicey, Introduction to the Study of the Constitution (http://www.constitution.org/cmt/avd/law_con.htm)

[164] Rivka Weil, Dicey was not Diceyan (CLJ [2003] 575)

[165] Athens called itself a democracy because all ÔcitizensÕ could take part in political decisions, but neither woman nor slaves were citizens Ð the quorum of this Athenian democracy was less than half.  Iaian McLean, The Concise Dictionary of Politics (OUP, Oxford, 1996)

[166] Iaian McLean, The Concise Dictionary of Politics (OUP, Oxford, 1996)

[167] Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996)

[168] Vernon Bogdanor, Power and the People, a Guide to Constitutional Reform (Victor Gollancz, 1997) p135

[169] Vernon Bogdanor, Power and the People, a Guide to Constitutional Reform (Victor Gollancz, 1997) p131

[170] Rodney Brazier, Constitutional Reform (2nd ed., Oxford 1998)

[171] A double majority combines a specific quorum and a specific majority Ð both have to be obtained before the result is valid.

[172] Mads Qvortrup, A Comparative Study of Referendums Ð Government by the People (Manchester University Press, Manchester, 2002) p15

[173] Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996) p42

[174] Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996) p43

[175] Vernon Bogdanor qualifies his suggestion with reference to evidence from Northern Ireland in Vernon Bogdanor, Our New Constitution [2004] LQR 120, 242

[176] Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996) p42

[177] Richard Lung, When knowledge fails belief: referendums (www.voting.ukscientist.com/referend.htm

[178] See below on Ômulti-choiceÕ referendums in Ôthe question to be putÕ and Fn 185

[179]  Lijphart asserts that governments only hold referendums when they are certain that they will win Arend Lijphart, Democracies.  Patterns of Majoritarian and Consensus Government in Twenty-One Countruies (Yale University Press, New Haven, 1984) p 203

[180] NB> The Electoral Commission has publicly disapproved of such a plan.

[181] in Joseph F. Zimmerman, Participatory Democracy Ð Populism Revived (Praeger Publishers, 1986)

[182] New Zealand appointed this system in its referendums on the reform of the electoral system. Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums, (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996) p48

[183] Cronin, Direct Democracy, the Politics of Initiative, Referendum and Recall (Harvard University Press, 1989) p161

[184] For example, citizens may be required to answer Ôstrongly agreeÕ, ÔagreeÕ, ÔindifferentÕ, ÔdisagreeÕ and Ôstrongly disagreeÕ with respect to a statement.

[185] Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996) Guidance 10

[186] A Multi-choice referendum is a referendum where voters are asked to pick their preferred option from a selection but are not asked to rank the options in order of preference.

[187] Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996) p51

[188] Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996) p49

[189] NB> Compromise and Discussion are widely considered to be some of the most important building-blocks of democracy.

[190] Dawn Oliver, Constitutional Reform in the UK (Oxford University Press, 2003)

[191] Dawn Oliver, Constitutional Reform in the UK (Oxford University Press, 2003)

[192] Magleby, Direct Legislation, Voting on Ballot Propositions in the United States (The John Hopkins University Press, 1984) p 98

[193] Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996) guidance 9

[194] Dawn Oliver, Constitutional Reform in the UK (Oxford University Press, 2003)

[195] Canadian Parliamentary Research Branch, Referendums: the Canadian Experience in an International Context (Law and Government Division, 1992)  section C provides a detailed analysis of the effect of the actual question on referendum results.

[196] Cronin, Direct Democracy, the Politics of Initiative, Referendum and Recall (Harvard University Press, 1989)

[197] Commission on the Conduct of Referendums, Report of the Commission on Referendums (Constitution Unit & Electoral Reform Society, 1996) para 12.32

[198] s.110 in particular which concerns assistance to protagonists in referendum campaigns

[199] Referendum on United Kingdom Membership of the European Community, 26 February 1975, Cmnd 5925

[200] See Fifth Report of the Committee on Standards in Public Life, Standards in Public Life; the funding of Political Parties in the United Kingdom 12.9

[201] See Fifth Report of the Committee on Standards in Public Life, Standards in Public Life; the funding of Political Parties in the United Kingdom

[202] See Fifth Report of the Committee on Standards in Public Life, Standards in Public Life; the funding of Political Parties in the United Kingdom 12.10

[203] Tom Baldwin and Rosemary Bennett, Referendum law unworkable, says watchdog (Times online April 24, 2004) www.timesonline.co.uk/printFriendly/0,,1-2-1085888-2,00.html

[204] Tom Baldwin and Rosemary Bennett, Referendum law unworkable, says watchdog (Times online April 24, 2004) www.timesonline.co.uk/printFriendly/0,,1-2-1085888-2,00.html

[205] Neil OÕBrien is the Campaign Director for the ÔVote NoÕ campaign for the referendum on the European Constitution

[206] BBC News, Euro Referendum gets Green Light, BBC Online, http://news.bbc.co.uk/go/pr/fr/-/hi/uk_politics/4034715.stm

[207] BBC News, Euro Referendum gets Green Light, BBC Online, http://news.bbc.co.uk/go/pr/fr/-/hi/uk_politics/4034715.stm

[208] This data is available for approximately ¾ of the campaigns in this period.

[209] Schmidt, Citizen Lawmakers (Temple University Press, Philadelphia, 1989) p 35

[210] David M. Farrell & Rudiger Schnitt-Beck (eds), Do Political Campaigns Matter? Campaign Effects in elections and referendums (Routledge / ECPR Studies in European Political Sciences, 2002) p191

[211] David M Farrell and Rudiger Schmitt-Beck (eds) Do Political Campaigns Matter? Ð campaign effects in elections and referendums (Routledge, ECPR studies in Eeuropean Political Sciences, 2002) p191

[212] A. H. Birch, Representative and Responsible Government (George Allen and Unwin Ltd, 1964)

[213] David M. Farrell & Rudiger Schnitt-Beck (eds), Do Political Campaigns Matter? Campaign Effects in elections and referendums (Routledge / ECPR Studies in European Political Sciences, 2002) p191

[214] ss. 126-127 in particular.

[215] A H Birch Representative and responsible Government (George Allen and Unwin Ltd, 1964)

[216] See Fifth Report of the Committee on Standards in Public Life, Standards in Public Life; the funding of Political Parties in the United Kingdom 12.12(1)

[217] In 1975 Harold Wilson agreed to suspend the convention of collective responsibility for the duration of the referendum campaign. Vernon Bogdanor, Power and the People, a Guide to Constitutional Reform (Victor Gollancz, 1997) p25, it is unclear whether Mr Blair will allow his ministers the same freedom.

[218] Ian Budge, The New Challenge of Direct Democracy (Blackwell, 1996) p88

[219] See Fifth Report of the Committee on Standards in Public Life, Standards in Public Life; the funding of Political Parties in the United Kingdom recommendation 89

[220] Indeed there are rumours that Tony Blair will continue to hold referendums on the Constitution for Europe until a ÔyesÕ vote is secured.

[221] Vernon Bogdanor in Ch 3 p45, David Butler & Austin Ranney (eds), Referendums Around the World, The Growing use of Direct Democracy (Macmillan, 1994)

[222] A M Green On-line discussion concerning the legal basis for national referendums in Britain www.iniref.org/natref1.html

[223] Iaian McLean, The Concise Dictionary of Politics (OUP, Oxford, 1996)

[224] Iaian McLean, The Concise Dictionary of Politics (OUP, Oxford, 1996)

[225] Cronin, Direct Democracy, the Politics of Initiative, Referendum and Recall (Harvard University Press, 1989) p231

[226] Ian Budge, The New Challenge of Direct Democracy (Blackwell, 1996) p89

[227] Joseph F. Zimmerman, Participatory Democracy Ð Populism Revived (Praeger Publishers, 1986)

[228] See, for example, criticism of the terrorism acts.

[229] Ian Budge, The New Challenge of Direct Democracy (Blackwell, 1996) p4

[230] See Institute of Public Policy Research, Is the Online Community a Policy Tool?

[231] Richard Lung, When knowledge fails belief: Referendums (www.voting.ukscientist.com/referend.htm

[232] Markku Suski, Bringing in the People, A Comparison of  Constitutional Form and Practices of the Referendum (Martinus Nijhoft Publishers, 1993)

[233] Vernon Bogdanor, Referendums and Separatism II in Ausitn Ranney (ed) The Referendum Device (Washington DC: American Enterprise Instutute, 1981) in Mads Qvortrup, A Comparative Study of Referendums Ð Government by the People (Manchester University Press, Manchester, 2002)

[234] Markku Suksi, Bringing in the People, A comparison of Constitutional Forms and Practices of the Referendum (Martinus Nijhoft publishers, 1993)

[235] Bruce Ackerman, We the People: Foundations (Belknap Press, Cambridge Mass. 1998)

[236] Quintin Oliver in Vote 2004, BlairÕs referendums www.vote-2004.com

[237] Magleby, Direct Legislation, Voting on Ballot Propositions in the United States (The John Hopkins University Press, 1984)

[238] Such a power exists in France.

[239] Or of course a list of sections of statutes which are constitutional would serve the same ends.

[240] See above re : defining the constitution.

[241] As advocated by Rodney Brazier and Tony Wright MP

[242] As per William Lawton, On-line discussion concerning the legal basis for national referendums in Britain www.iniref.org/natref1.html

[243] Bogdanor in Magleby, Direct Legislation, Voting on Ballot Propositions in the United States (The John Hopkins University Press, 1984) p 30

[244] See Neville Lindsay at http://www.iniref.org/direct.or.indirect.html : ÒThe ballot initiative process in California was recently subverted to allow a tiny percentage of the population to dictate to the rest of us what meat we are allowed to eat, for heavens sake! With only a 28% turnout, an initiative to ban the sale of horse meat passed by 51%. That's less than 15% of the registered  voters, or about 6% of the population, dictating to the rest of us what goes into our larders.Ó

[245] Joseph F. Zimmerman, Participatory Democracy Ð Populism Revived (Praeger Publishers, 1986)

[247] CitizensÕ Initative and Referendum, Proposal for the Introduction of New Democratic procedures in Great Britain and Northern Ireland http://www.iniref.org/steps.html  

[248] Nigel Smith in Vote 2004, BlairÕs referendums www.vote-2004.com

[249] E C S Wade in Dicey Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (12th ed. Macmillan & Co. Ltd, London, 1959)

[250] Bogdanor in Magleby, Direct Legislation, Voting on Ballot Propositions in the United States (The John Hopkins University Press, 1984) p33